Let’s assume that the meaning of marriage is infinitely malleable,
that it is a social construct and can mean whatever we choose for it to
mean in the way that twentieth-century art came to basically include anything anyone wanted it to include.
If that were the case, then it would make any remaining restrictions
on what can count as marriage merely arbitrary. Faced with the logic of
this nominalist turn, this is exactly what some people are now arguing.
In
an article last month for Slate,
Jillian Keenan suggested that the meaning of marriage is endlessly
elastic. The topic of her article was polygamy, but the principle of
marital plasticity might be taken in any number of other directions:
“The definition of marriage is plastic.
Just like heterosexual marriage is no better or worse than homosexual
marriage, marriage between two consenting adults is not inherently more
or less “correct” than marriage among three (or four, or six) consenting
adults. Though polygamists are a minority—a tiny minority, in
fact—freedom has no value unless it extends to even the smallest and
most marginalized groups among us. So let’s fight for marriage equality
until it extends to every same-sex couple in the United States—and then
let’s keep fighting. We’re not done yet”
My point in quoting this is not to invoke a slippery slope argument
that legalizing “gay marriage” will lead to legalizing polygamy.
Alastair Roberts
is right
that since same-sex “marriage” is by far the more radical aberration,
“expressing a concern that same-sex marriage might lead to polygamy
would be akin to worry on our part that mainlining heroin might lead to
experimentation with marijuana.” Moreover, for all its problems and
gender inequality, polygamy is still marriage since it involves sexual
dimorphism (at least, if the conclusion of this article be accepted).
Rather, the problem in Keenan’s perspective is more basic: once we
accept the narrative that marriage is plastic, then there is no
theoretical limit that can determine when the marriage modernizers are
actually finished. If marriage is so plastic that it can mean absolutely
anything, then in another sense it means nothing at all.
It is significant in this regard that
dozens of public figures
(including leading activists, scholars, educators, writers, artists,
lawyers, journalists, and community organizers) have now signed a joint
statement titled, “
Beyond Same-Sex Marriage: A New Strategic Vision for All Our Families and Relationships.”
This statement argues that those who are advancing same-sex “marriage”
have not gone far enough. Invoking a fallacious is-ought line of
reasoning, the statement argues that since traditional nuclear families
are no longer the norm, government needs to be more elastic in what it
considers to be “legitimate families.” They write, “The struggle for
same-sex marriage rights is only one part of a larger effort to
strengthen the security and stability of diverse households and
families.” How diverse? The Statement suggests that anyone living
together should be considered a family, including “Close friends and
siblings who live together in long-term, committed, non-conjugal
relationships...” It also suggests that “legitimate families” can
involve people who don’t live together, including “Queer couples who
decide to jointly create and raise a child with another queer person or
couple, in two households.”
If these examples illustrate anything, it is that once we concede
that marriage (and therefore family) are social constructs, these
categories become so wide that they tend to be evacuated of coherent
meaning.
Once we concede that marriage has no essential meaning but is
entirely culturally relative, then the only thing left to give fixity to
marriage is whatever the majority happens to say. We see this happening
in much of the public debate about same-sex marriage, where
journalists, media commentators and even lawyers are increasingly
appealing to the herd for validation of their positions.
|
Andrew Koppelman, the John Paul
Stevens Professor of Law at Northwestern University |
This was the approach taken by Andrew Koppelman, the John Paul
Stevens Professor of Law at Northwestern University. When defending “gay
marriage” against Sherif Girgis in
a fascinating debate at the Harvard Law School,
Koppelman began his argument by citing statistics showing how many
people now accept same-sex “marriage”, as if his opinion was proved
right through majority consensus. As Koppelman continued his
presentation, one of the key points in his response to Girgis was not
that Girgis’ arguments for the conjugal view were illogical (although he
did allege that in a different part of the debate), but that most
ordinary people wouldn’t be able to understand them. Koppelman’s implied
premise was that same-sex “marriage” was above critique because it had
the understanding of the majority.
It sounds strange that any intelligent person could imagine that
having the support of 51% of the country makes a policy position
correct. However, if marriage is entirely relative to the cultural
moment, then what else could determine the boundaries of marriage other
than majority opinion? A parallel would be the moves in the game of
chess, which achieve their legitimacy purely through majority consensus.
Koppelman actually invoked this example in the aforementioned debate,
pointing out that the move that the knight is allowed to make wasn’t
always how we know it today, but evolved over hundreds of years. Just as
there is no objective essence to chess which determines that the knight
has to move in the way it does, so there is no objective
essence to marriage which determines that it has to mean one thing and
not another thing. It is entirely a cultural construct.
Read more...